In Memoriam

Past, Present, and Future,
A Philosophical Essay

by Irwin C. Lieb,
Illinois University Press, 1991

The Moving Finger writes; and, having writ,
Moves on:  nor all your Piety nor Wit
     Shall lure it back to cancel half a Line,
Nor all your Tears wash out a Word of it.

Edward FitzGerald, The Rubáiyát of Omar Khayyám
[Dover Publications, 1990, §71, p.42]


Καὶ ὁ ἄγγελος... ὤμοσεν... ὅτι χρόνος οὐκέτι ἔσται.

And the angel... swore... that time will be no more.

Revelation 10:5-6

Irwin C. Lieb (1925-1992), BA Princeton, 1947, MA Cornell, 1949, and PhD Yale, 1953, began teaching at the University of Texas, where I later knew him, in 1963. I considered attending UT in 1972, while Lieb was the Chairman of the Philosophy Department (1968-1972); and he seems to have remembered me when I did become a graduate student there in 1975. Meanwhile, he had become Vice-President and Dean of Graduate Studies (1975-1979). Nevertheless, despite the lofty administrative post, he was my advisor in the time until my dissertation committee was formed. He seems to have taken an interest in me because as a student he had read Leonard Nelson and was intrigued that I sought to promote Nelson through my work. His own work, however, did not seem to reflect any use of Nelson's Friesian philosophy.

In 1981, Lieb moved to the University of Southern California (USC), where he had administrative and teaching posts, including Vice President and Dean of the College of Letters, Arts, and Sciences (1982-1986). He gained some general notariety in 1983 by negotiating the emigration of seven Soviet Jewish scientists, "refuseniks," who had been denied exit visas from the Soviet Union. Spending considerable time in Los Angeles and then living there after graduating in 1985, I saw Lieb two or three times before he came down with cancer and passed away in 1992 -- aged a year younger than I am now in 2017. I did not realize how bad he was until receiving an invitation to attend his memorial service [note]. Lieb's friends called him "Chet," but I do not seem to have ever been that intimate.

In Austin, I had taken a seminar with Lieb on time, about which he was writing a book. The book took a while to complete, and it came out just a year before his death. His dedication apologizes for having taken so long. Since he had said a number of striking things about time in the seminar, I was looking forward to seeing the book when published. At first, however, I had some trouble getting into it. Later I met a philosophy professor from USC who had known Lieb and who didn't seem to think that the book was very good. However, perhaps with the greater wisdom, or patience, of age, I am now finding it more accessible and interesting. It has its flaws but also its virtues, not the least of which is such a sustained effort to tackle the subject in the first place. I think that there are few efforts in the history of philosophy to develop an extensive metaphysics of time. Lieb has done that, with a fair number of provocative claims and arguments, even if in the end I must judge the effort unsuccessful.

He also has written a book, without footnotes or bibliography, that pretty much ignores contemporary philosophy -- unlike most academic philosophy, where so-and-so who is at Columbia or Berkeley or Oxford, saying this, that, or the other, is often mentioned every sentence or so, with references opaque to anyone not in on recent literature or debates. Lieb's argument addresses Classical philosophers from Plato to Alfred North Whitehead, with the only exception that I see of Paul Weiss (1901-2002). And while we get his thanks in the "Acknowledgments" to several academic colleagues, the only one of the sort who appears in the text, at least identified by name, is Charles Hartshorne (1897-2000). Some recent doctrines are discussed, but without attribution. This practice appears to contradict Lieb's own advice to me, which was that my work didn't pay much attention to "current" problems and discussion. This, career-wise, wasn't "smart." Indeed, it wasn't [note].

But I did not find the popular preoccupations in academic philosophy either engaging or edifying, agreeing with Karl Popper's statement that recent philosophy involves a "concentration upon minutiae (upon 'puzzles') and especially upon the meanings of words; in brief .... scholasticism," and with Allan Bloom, who said, "Professors of these schools [i.e. positivism and ordinary language analysis] simply would not and could not talk about anything important, and they themselves do not represent a philosophic life for the students."

Thus, from the evidence of his book, Irwin Lieb did not practice what he preached. The result, however, does represent "a philosophic life." The seminar on time was the only class I had with him, and he was consistently engaging, witty, earnest, and provocative. I wish all my graduate seminars had been at such a level, both philosophically and pedagogically [note].

A basic problem with Lieb's book and his treatment of time is his unproblematic use of the divisions of time as "past, present, and future." As in the title. This is accepted without question, without discussion, and without comparison to any alternatives. Indeed, this is not unusual; and most philosophers dealing with anything about time would probably express some perplexity at the idea that there are any alternatives to the division of past, present, and future. Isn't this self-evident? Yet Lieb himself lived in a time, both as a student and a professor, of so-called "linguistic philosophy," when the role of language was a matter of intense concern in Anglo-American philosophy, and elsewhere, with whole systems built around particular claims about language. Theories and critiques about language sometimes replaced whole areas of philosophy, such as epistemology, metaphysics, or ethics.

Since most of "linguistic philosophy" was actually ill informed about natural languages and was little more than a smoke screen for the promotion of unrelated and generally discreditable philosophical doctrines -- the Logical Positivists were absolutely the worst in that regard -- I cannot count it as a fault that Lieb seems to ignore all of it in his book. Nevetheless, there is an area where informed knowledge about languages might have helped in dealing with time. This concerns the actual inflection of verbs for time, which may use a "tense" system of past, present, and future, an "aspect" system of aorist, perfect, and imperfect, both of those systems, or neither. Sometimes linguistic philosophers or people in linguistics like the idea that languages where verbs have no temporal inflection are used by people who have no awareness of time. This is absurd, but philosophers apparently have not carried that thought forward into the substantive and fruitful project of devoting attention to the aspect systems.

There is considerable irony in this. Languages with the most complete combination of tense and aspect systems include Modern English and Classical Greek. People in philosophy generally have some knowledge of one or the other of those languages but seem unaware of the aspect systems. And this is nothing new. Greek philosophers themselves did not notice the aspect system in their own language but began the tradition of thinking exclusively in terms of past, present, and future. Yet in the subjunctive and imperative moods, Greek verbs are only inflected for aspect. Thus, Aristotle's analysis of "future contingency" in On Interpretation would have been stronger and made better sense as "imperfect contingency." Yet Aristotle overlooked, we might say, this aspect of the matter [note].

And it is noteworthy that to some linguistic philosophers, this should be impossible. Aristotle would have been required and compelled by the grammar of his language to think about aspect as well as tense. But he didn't -- which discredits certain claims in linguistic philosophy. Thus, the structure of his language did not compel him to think about the world, reflectively, in a certain way, despite using the language and its structure (unreflectively) every day of his life.

The further irony is that, while I have no idea how observant he was, Irwin Lieb was Jewish -- at least the memorial service for him that I attended was conducted by a rabbi -- and this probably means that as a child he studied Hebrew to a greater or lesser extent. But Hebrew is one of the languages that only inflects for aspect -- in fact, as is typical, only for the perfect and imperfect (often called "perfective" and "imperfective") aspects -- , qâṭal, "he has killed, killed," , yiqṭōl, "he is killing, will kill" (Arabic , qaṭala). This is not unusual, and this type of inflection can also be found in the related language of Arabic (, faʿala, "he has done, did"; , yafʿalu, "he is doing, will do") and in the (quite) unrelated languages Russian and Japanese [note].

Thus, Lieb, in order to be insensible of aspect inflection, needed to ignore his native language as an American, the language of his ancestral religion, and the language, Greek, with which, as a traditionally educated philosopher, he may well have had some kind of familiarity. Actually, the aspect system (and the auxiliary verb system) probably was not even identified as such in the grammar that used to be taught in primary and secondary education -- where now no grammar may be taught at all (it's elitist). At least, if Lieb had no interest in linguistic philosophy, his neglect might be understandable. But the linguistic philosophers themselves, sometimes openly contemptuous of natural languages (thanks to the Positivists), cannot have the same kind of excuse.

Well, one might think, so what? What difference does it make if we are aware of temporal aspect as well as tense? Well, time looks a bit different. The perfect and imperfect can both be used as present tenses. The perfect is for actions just completed ("we've just had dinner"), and the imperfect for those continuing ("we're having dinner right now"). But then the imperfect stretches into the future, and can be used for the future tense; and the perfect stretches into the past, and can be used for the past tense. Where ambiguity would be a problem, Arabic uses particles, , qad, to specify the perfect as past ( , "he did"), and , sawfa, to specify the imperfect as future ( , "he will do"). This actually fits into Lieb's analysis and system better than the tense divisions. An important contention by Lieb is that the present contains two processes, the coming-to-be and the passing-away. Philosophers have mostly ignored the presence of the latter, and this duality is something that we just do not see in previous philosophy. So Lieb has an important insight.

But it is all the clearer what this means when we look at aspect rather than tense. There we already have the duality. Also, Lieb argues at length that the past and the future are real; but with the perfect and imperfect, the reality of the past and the future is already included when we affirm that the perfect and imperfect are real in the present. In the first place, this at least alters the terms of the metaphysical challenge. Thus, if we begin with the idea that things do not exist in the past and the future, then Lieb must argue that, in some sense, they do. On the other hand, if we allow that things exist in the perfect and imperfect, the problem contra Lieb, more challenging, is to argue how each aspect must itself be divided into the real and the unreal. The burden of proof has shifted, to Lieb's advantage. It is a shame that Lieb could derive no benefit from this.

Accepting the dualism of perfect and imperfect immediately suggests a connection to traditional metaphysics. In Aristotle, the substances of the world consist of form and matter. Form is what is actual (ἐνέργεια, actualitas), fixed, and definite. Matter is what is potential, possible, and powerful (δύναμις, potentia). This opens a door big enough to drive a truck through. Form is obviously what is aspectually perfect. Matter is obviously what is aspectually imperfect. Just how this works is to be determined. Are perfect and imperfect time functions of form and matter; or is it the other way around? Which underlies which? Whichever it is, Lieb, tied to tenses, has missed his chance here, where traditional Aristotelian form and matter seem rather too passive and inert for what would be demanded of them. Without the tools of aspect in hand, it never occurs to Lieb to just upgrade the Aristotelian conceptions. The imperfect, as "matter," is future time flowing to the present, while the perfect, as "form," is present time flowing into the past -- even as Lieb says that "Aristotle's doctrine about the form and matter of substances can be thought of as a static analogue of this kind of forming, the inner and outer activity" [p.156]. The perfect and imperfect would animate the "static analogue."

To approach the major problems with Lieb's treatment, let me begin with a quote in medias res:

The past consists of what was becoming definite in a present; it became fully definite in being past. The past consists of what is fully actual. While individuals are present they are becoming definite and actual, and the completion of that process is their being past. Individuals are transformed when they become past, and the most prominent change in them is that their singularity is lost. In the present, individuals are singular and extended; they resist and oppose one another. They are spatial and outside one another. None of these features becomes past. What becomes past is the definiteness the individuals have achieved from inside themselves, and the definiteness of each individual is joined with the definiteness of all the other individuals that were their contemporaries. Together, they are the achieved definiteness of a moment of the entire world, joined to the past to which they have conformed. There is one whole past. There is no space in it and it has no length; duration and spatiality are only in a present time. [p.126]

Key features of Lieb's metaphysics are on display in this passage. Most important is the assertion of the actuality of the past, within which individuals remain actual, as they have been in the future and the present. Lieb's whole system is built on the actuality of individuals in past, present, and future. However, we note that there is something distinctive about individuals in the present. They are "singular," which is an attribute that they have achieved in the present but then lose, as asserted here, as they become past.

So what does it mean to be "singular"? Lieb really does never explain how this differs from being "individual," except that it is something that individuals are in the present but not otherwise. This is a problem because the "singular" in logic simply means the quantification of an individual. Socrates, in not being a universal, is a singular [note]. So Lieb's terminology is threatened with a redundancy and a distinction without a difference. But what would the difference be? Well, he uses "singular" where anyone else might use "exist." Individuals exist in the present, but not in the past or future. Since Lieb wants to say that the past and future, and their individuals, both exist as much as the present, he has some explaining to do; and I really don't see that he ever does it. Leaving the terms "individual" and "singular" where the only differentiation in the meaning is that "singular" is a substitute for "exists" may add up to no more than a bit of sophistry.

This is disastrous for his theory, since his most basic claims, and all of his argument and theory, are tied to it. Thus, if in becoming past, individuals lose their singularity, their extension, their causal interaction with others, and even their duration, why not just say they lose everything, as in "they cease to exist" and all their features disappear with them? What is preserved by the past, Lieb says, is the "definiteness" achieved in the present. Indeed, they only become "fully definite" in being past. However, this raises another difficulty. What difference does this full definiteness make? If individuals lose their capacity to "resist and oppose one another," i.e. causally interact, then their "definiteness" cannot affect anything else and make any physical difference. It is lost, just as much as in the traditional view that things become nothing as they become past.

In the effect of the past on the present, Lieb is more than a little careless. He is sensible that the formation of the present is dependent on immediately past conditions; but in considering the "historical past" he does not carefully distinguish between the immediate or proximate past and the more remote past. The more remote past cannot have an effect on the present, as he concedes, except by way of causal products that still exist in the immediate past. Lieb can write about the information possessed by historians as though it has been directly caused by the remote past. He otherwise knows that this does not happen. The "weight of the past" consists only of causal fragments in the immediate past. That which fades from the immediate past can be immediately lost. In trying to reconstruct the past, we have evidence that suffers from the problem of a "noise to signal ratio." The noise increases over time, as the past becomes more remote and its causal remnants decay, and this is a function of a fundamental law of nature, namely, entropy. Thus, the evidence that remains from the past, which is all that we have access to, erodes and degrades, which means it becomes more chaotic as disorder overwhelms order.

With aspect, we can make a distinction that Lieb does not. The immediate past is, of course, the perfect aspect in the present. It is an active part of a causal event, representing the conditions that occasion the application and manifestation of a natural law, resulting in an effect; and it possesses the definiteness Lieb attributes to the past. However, the perfect aspect outside the present then constitutes the remote and increasingly remote past, and it is not the active part of any causal event. It has lost all the features that Lieb has detailed; and even the definiteness that he says it retains and, apparently, perfects(!) is lost to any interaction with present individuals. That might leave us wondering, what difference does it make to say, as Lieb does, that the past exists? It's features are lost to any means of interaction with the present. Lieb can obscure this because the proximate and the remote past are lumped together, without the distinction we must make between the perfect aspect in the present and that which is not. So Lieb's argument for the existence of the past seems to rest on an ambiguity that is allowed by his neglect of temporal aspect, allowing him to speak of "the past" both in terms of active presence of the perfect and the inactive state of the remote past, which is the perfect aspect outside the present.

We see another peculiar feature of Lieb's theory in the following quote:

Singularity is a moment of the being of individuals, it is the present moment, and when individuals are singular they continuously reconstitute themselves as time continously passes into and through them, making them past. Individuals are not identical over a period of time in the same way that Aristotelian substances or [Paul] Weissian actualities are the same, without a change of their being; they are the same by reconstituting themselves, by forming their future being to continue what they already are, and by having what they already are continuously become more and more definite and then finally definite as past. Singular individuals are moments of self-formation in the being of individuals. The passing portions of individuals are their being as past contribute to this forming. They contribute to the growing definiteness in singular individuals. [p.155]

First of all, here we have a discussion of "singularity" that makes a number of assertions about it but does not clarify the obscurity of its nature or argue for the cogency of Lieb's use of the concept. Instead, we see another important feature of Lieb's theory, that individuals in the present are in the act of continuously "reconstituting themselves" as "moments of self-formation." They "continuously become more and more definite," but not completely so until they are past.

In all of this, Lieb is in effect in a running battle, not just with Aristotle and others, but with physics. Occasionally he notices that a scientific physical theory of matter is out there, but he avoids a direct confrontation, sometimes even seems to classify "atoms" or "particles" as not being "individuals" in the way that he uses the term, and on top of it sometimes even seems to confuse the terms of Greek Atomism with modern particle physics. Indeed, modern particles would not fit well in his theory.

The worst case for Lieb's whole theory is the nature of the photon. Photons are field quanta of electro-magnetism, have zero rest mass, and spontaneously move at the velocity of light. This means that, in terms of Special Relativity, time does not pass in the frame of reference of the photon. This reality, if it is one, threatens to falsify Lieb's entire theory of time. The passing of time is fundamental to Lieb's metaphysics, since individuals only remain "singular" in the present by "reconstituting themselves"; but according to Albert Einstein, time does not pass at the velocity of light. Photos cannot "reconstitute" themselves because they do not exist in the kind of time that allows for change. There can be no change if time does not pass. And, indeed, nothing about a photon changes in the course of its existence.

This is only the beginning of the trouble. Even a particle like an electron, which does not move at the velocity of light, possesses the characteristics of a classical substance. Lieb doesn't accept this. But a substance does not need to "reconstitute" itself because it endures through time in its essence. The character of a classical substance is that it is durable, separable, and identical. This fits electrons as well as Aristotelian substances. But if an electron as a Liebian "individual" must continuously "reconstitute" itself to endure, it is not clear what sort of physical process this could be. Indeed, physics will allow no such process. The electron endures because its character is defined by certain conserved physical properties, such as mass, lepton number, charge, etc. The position and momentum of the particle can change, without change in the nature of the particle. A physical process can change an electron into something else, but no physical process is necessary, or even possible, for an electron to endure as it is. This is now built into the foundations of physics.

It is not clear to me why Lieb needs to reject the conception of the classical substance. In the whole book, the impression we get of the passage of time is like a head wind, in which time blows out of the future, is processed by individuals in the present, and then blows away parts of them, or perhaps all of them, into the past. The idea that the wind might just whip around certain things, substances, doesn't seem worth considering. Why this commitment? The precedent seems to be Whitehead's "actual entities," whose momentary existence precludes substance but then also, as in Buddhist metaphysics, leaves the problem of identity. If a thing now is identical to the thing that existed a moment ago, or years ago, something must endure; but I do not think that Lieb addresses or considers this issue -- assuming the continuity of identity in individuals without responding to the "momentariness" difficulties that arise in the metaphysics of Whitehead or Buddhism. And if individuals consist of matter, then they are a sum of particles whose durability and identity is posited in modern physics (although individual identity can actually be lost in quantum superpositions -- where, nevertheless, conserved quantities are preserved and endure).

Nowhere is Lieb's metaphysics so awkwardly shadowed by modern physics as in his treatment of Greek Atomism from pages 172 though 175. Although ostensively a discussion of Greek Atomism, at moments this also seems to encompass atoms or particles in recent physics, as when Lieb says about multiple "forces" that act on atoms that "Currently, there are thought to be even more" [p.173]. "Currently" what and by whom? He does not let us know. What is he talking about? I can't say. Indeed, the whole discussion of "forces," if it is only about Greek Atomism, seems to go well beyond the sophistication of Greek materialism yet is also pointless in badly misrepresenting what a "force" is in modern physics. A particularly confusing, or confused, passage is this:

It is difficult to understand how a moving atom transmits a force and how and when that force is efficacious. It seems that it should be efficacious all along or at least that it should be expended all along; it is implausible that a carried force should diminish or disappear and then increase or reappear when it is transmitted in a collision. Still, if a force is efficacious while it is carried in an atom, there is some question as to why it does not continuously accelerate the atom that carries it. When, where, and how impressed, latent, or potential forces are efficacious and why they are not dissipated is at best an obscure matter. We are uncertain, even now, what forces do. [p.173, color added]

The consolation that Lieb is only talking about Greek Atomism, if we wanted to comfort ourselves that way, is instantly exploded by the "even now" that is added here. One thing we certainly know is that a "force" is not "carried in an atom." In motion, a particle or atom, or macroscopic body, "carries" kinetic energy, not a "force." The "force" does not "diminish or disappear" or dissipate because of the principle of the conservation of energy. This is not an "obscure matter" but one of the most fundamental principles in physics.

It is not "difficult to understand" how a moving body transmits a force. As the application of a force may have accelerated the body to the velocity it possesses, a collision results in a deceleration (under the same Newtonian rule of F=ma), transmitting kenetic energy to the impacted body and accelerating it. This is Physics 101. Since neither body "carries" the force, no question arises about whether "it should be efficacious all along or at least that it should be expended all along." The force was already expended. Nor does any question arise over whether "it is implausible that a carried force should diminish or disappear and then increase or reappear when it is transmitted in a collision." Again, no "force" is "carried" by an atom, particle, or body. It cannot "diminish or disappear" because all that is "carried" by the body is energy, which is conserved and so cannot be created or destroyed. So no "force" needs to "increase or reappear" in a collision, since some or all of the kinetic energy of the body becomes the force that accelerates the impacted body. There is no "question as to why it does not continuously accelerate the atom that carries it." The atom "carries" no force, only kinetic energy. Energy is the ability to do work; and in a collision, work gets done.

Again, there is nothing obscure about this, as long as one is aware of the difference between force (the unit of the Newton, N=kg*m/s2) and energy (the Joule, J=kg*m2/s2). Since Lieb has no mention or discussion of energy in this passage, or indeed, as far as I have noticed, in the entire book, he is lacking the basic materials to answer the questions that he raises here. Nor can we, again, console ourselves that this is only the primitive physics of the Greek Atomists, for Lieb betrays his thinking that these issues have not changed since then and, if they had, he then owes us some treatment in the book of the modern physics of force and energy since, as energy is the ability to do work, it is requisite for any physical changes that would ever be evident with the passage of time. We don't get that treatment, nor any awareness that his constant assertions about the activity of individuals in the present has a physical reality requiring the passage, not just of time, but of physical energy. But since the durability of a photon or electron over time does not require the expenditure of energy, this is a falsifying embarrassment to his entire theory. There is also the not inconsiderable irony that the Aristotelian term for the actuality of a substance, ἐνέργεια, actually is the modern word "energy."

Lieb's discussion continues with more indications of confusion between past and present physics:

The time for the expenditure of forces is different. Forces are carried by atoms: an atom may transmit some or all of the forces that are in it, but it can never be without some force, and that force is always being expended on or from inside it. Inside an atom, then, there is always a passing expenditure of force, and no clocks or other motions can measure it. There is only an indirect measure of an amount of force, calculated by inferring the force from the motions of atoms. Since force is not dissipated, the total force for all the atoms is thought to remain the same, though there has been recent speculation that the quantity of force in a closed system of particles might be reduced over a period of time. [p.174, color added]

Any, perhaps fading, hope that Lieb is only talking about Greek Atomism cannot survive the references to force being "calculated," which the Greeks never did, and to "recent speculation," which cannot mean "recent" Greek Atomists. His paragraph continues with similar, painful confusion.

The situation within modern atoms is somewhat different than with the previous references to moving and colliding atoms. Atoms are indeed held together by forces, namely the strong nuclear force and the electromagnetic force that holds electrons to the nucleus. If this is what Lieb means, he doesn't make it very clear; and if so, he apparently does not understand that these forces are not "expended" and do not experience "a passing expenditure." That has no physical meaning. As long as the nucleus and the electrons maintain their charges, electrical force will hold the atom together; and since the charges are conserved quantities, they cannot be "dissipated." The forces they exert not only are "thought to remain the same" but must remain the same under the currently understood laws of physics. The charges exert forces because they create fields of potential energy -- which is how the issue is different here from the kenetic energy of moving bodies. If there is some "recent speculation" that a "closed system of particles" can lose energy (not "force"), violating the conservation of energy, I have missed what it was all about. And Lieb, without footnotes, gives us no references.

Just how bad this is, and how inexcusable, we can see in one last quote on this issue:

It is not a factual matter whether forces can be dissipated:  the classical notion of force precludes dissipation. A force that can be dissipated -- whatever "dissipation" means -- is a force differently construed:  it is a kind of thing that can cease to be or cease being expended, and so construed it also would have to be the kind of thing that can come about. [p.175, color added]

However, there is no "classical notion of force" that "precludes dissipation." Thus, there is no principle of the "conservation of force," and Lieb here must be, again, confusing "force" with energy. And since he keeps talking about forces being "dissipated," which in this case seems to be a phenomenon of his own imagination, he cannot just dismiss the idea with "whatever 'dissipation' means." It is his business to tell us what he means by it.

These considerable confusions conceal the challenge that physics represents to Lieb's theory. The principal issues involved are Lieb's rejection of the character of substances and his idea that the persistence of particles, atoms, and bodies over time requires, instead of substantive durability, that they "continuously reconstitute themselves." If the latter is a physical process, then there ought to be some physical theory and evidence of that, which will require an expenditure of energy. But there is nothing of the sort in physics, where the very idea of conserved quantities, like mass, charge, etc., violates Lieb's view of time in the present as requiring some sort of constant process (as in Whitehead) just to preserve itself.

So, for Lieb to preserve his theory, he is better off obscuring these problems and avoiding a direct confrontation with the modern principles of physics. It would have been better to ignore them altogether, but his confusion in the matter goes deep enough that he does not seem to realize how vulnerable he makes himself by wandering from Greek Atomism into what he obviously thinks is its modern equivalent. But modern physics is a world of difference from any Greek physics, Atomist or otherwise. And so Lieb seems genuinely unaware of the muddle that his treatment displays and produces.

Lieb's treatments of possibility and of natural law leave me confused about what his theory adds up to. Possibility and natural law are both about the power and potential of coming-to-be, which means the imperfect aspect and so, in Lieb's terms, the future. However, Lieb has some sort of problem with this, which I'm not sure I even understand. To get into it, let me look at some things Lieb says:

The idea that most helps us to understand them, discussed earlier, is that individuals have depth and that they act outward from their depths even while they are forming themselves anew in those depths. Individuals are not unchanging substances or actualities whose changes or actions are incidental to what they really are. They are always changing, and they are not distinct from their changes, but they also last, and they do this by reconstituting themselves continuously. [p.111]

We've already got some of this picture, but I have not previously mentioned the business of the "depth" within which individuals are "forming themselves anew." This metaphorical "depth" is never explained, as far as I can tell, in any literal terms. Lieb uses a lot of metaphor. Time comes from within these "depths" and passes outside individuals in the course of their becoming past. I have said that Lieb's view of time is like a head wind -- "Time comes into individuals" -- which we might think comes from the outside, somehow; but Lieb actually has it coming from within.

From this, we might get the idea that Lieb is using something like Aristotle's view of matter, which is the power, the δύναμις, contained in individuals. But Lieb explicitly contradicts this:

Individuals have insides, they have depths, but they do not have reservoirs of power inside them. [p.112]

But if time from the future comes through the "depths" of individuals (what Schopenhauer might call "will"), it is hard to see how the power and possibility of the future is not just such a "reservoir." But Lieb does not take advantage of this. I can't say that he has a more sensible alternative; and I think it is revealing that Lieb uses a word like "incidental" when the classical, Aristotelian theory of substance would say "accidental" (accidens) instead. Discussion of the structure of substance or essence (οὐσία, essentia) and accident is something that we might expect from someone rejecting the classical idea of substance. But we don't get it. Otherwise, elaborating his ideas, we do get:

The passing time in individuals changes them by making them act outwardly and, as they act, by turning them inside out. Times does this as it itself passes outward from inside individuals to free itself from the hold individuals have on it. It thereby binds itself more closely with the time that had been inside other individuals and with the time that was outside them as the space of the present. [p.112]

The connection of time with space in this is entirely metaphorical and never given much of a literal explanation. Individuals getting turned "inside out" is a nice metaphor, but it is not something that we can literally see. The best I can do as an explanation is that as future time comes out of the "depths" into the present, it adds a new coming-to-be of the individual, when then, in passing outside, also passes into past time, adding and completing definiteness to the individual. Since real space only exists in the present, the coming-to-be of the individual empties into that, adding to the common pool created by all other individuals doing the same thing, in the present space that already existed outside them all in the first place. Elsewhere, Lieb has the idea that individuals dominate time in the future and that time overcomes individuals in the present and then dominates them in the past [p.114]. I can't say, after reading the whole book, what this really means. Metaphor dominates the theory. Individuals being turned "inside out" is a nice image, but I can't say what the literal metaphysics is supposed to amount to. Whether it is wind or water emptying out of individuals into the common space, we might want to know what that stuff is. Well, it's time; but then in a whole book of a theory about time, time remains essentially opaque.

Can possibilities explain that things change, or are changes better explained by the effectiveness of a real past rather than by something apart from time? [p.118]

Unfortunately, the proper metaphysical problem is not to ask "Can possibilities explain that things change," but to ask how our metaphysical theory can explain possibilities. Also, as we see here, Lieb's approach seems to be to load the answer into the past; but the past is actually devoid of possibility. It is fixed and definite, as Lieb admits himself. The future contains what is possible; and Aristotle's matter contains the power and potential of the future. Yet Lieb does not avail himself of what seems to me the quite obvious move, which is to collapse Lieb's idea of the actual future into the "depths" of Aristotelian matter, which is "inside" individuals precisely because it is the "underlying" thing -- ὑποκείμενον -- of individuals. Despite repeated discussions of Aristotle, Lieb somehow never really gets into details like this.

We choose among possibilities, or we think we do, and we enact what we have chosen. [p.119]

Choosing and enacting themselves require power (δύναμις, potens), which cannot be supplied by the past, where all is fixed, definite, and impotent. It is not at all obvious where this power comes from in Lieb's metaphysic. The obvious answer should be the "depths" where the indefiniteness and openness of the future pours into the indivdiual. But, as we have seen, individuals "do not have reservoirs of power inside them." So Lieb leaves us with a blank wall. And Lieb keeps adding bricks to that wall:

For Aristotle, the possibilities or potentialities of substances have no reality in themselves. The forms of everything that can possibly occur are already actualized in substances, somewhere and in some way... There is no separate domain of forms, no separate possibilites. [p.123]

Really? And why is this necessarily so? And if there is "no separate domain of... possibilties," what is the point of having a separate metaphysical domain of "matter" (ὕλη) that is really defined as containing "possibilities or potentialities"? Of course substances have no potentiality "in themselves" as substances, since the form (εἶδος) of substances is defined as the actuality (ἐνέργεια) of things. It is the matter that does the job of containing the "possibilities or potentialities." But Lieb abandons Aristotelian matter as inert.

When Lieb says "separate domain of forms," he is probably thinking of Plato's World of Forms. While Plato's Forms contain all possibilities, a drawback of Plato's theory was always how the Forms themselves occasion change or the "participation" of individual things in the character of the Form. Impressing the Forms on things could be done by the "Demiurge" of the Timaeus, but while Plato's presentation was of the Creation, a theory of ongoing change would require that the Demiurge keep doing this, constantly. There are philosophers, Occasionalists, who have precisely that theory, specifically Malebranche and Spinoza. Thus, perhaps it is not surprising to find Lieb saying in his "Acknowledgments" that "there was a Spinozistic strain in my ideas" [p.257].

Lieb also acknowledges a debt "most of all" to Plato; and this may provide a clue for what is going on here. The "domain of forms" in its definiteness and fixity displays a perfect aspect, which is a feature of the past rather than the future. I have identified this as a bias and a mistake in Western metaphysics. If Lieb incongruously associates possibility with the past, it may reflect this bias. But in the World of Forms, the definiteness and fixity of the Forms means that possibility is really the same thing as necessity, since both are based on precisely the same objects and structure.

Such a theory therefore cannot distinguish between possibility and necessity. This is a grave failure in any metaphysical theory, and it is hard not to attribute a similar failure to Lieb. Apart from something that amounts to actual dismissal of "possibilities," he says almost nothing about necessity, and I'm not sure that his treatment of natural law adds up to anything intelligible.

Possibility, necessity, and natural law all require structures in the source of change. In Lieb's metaphysics, this must mean the future. His future, however, is all "indefinite," and this seems to preclude a structure that would restrict, require, or prohibit particular events. When Lieb says, "The forms of everything that can possibly occur are already actualized in substances," this is a description of Aristotle's metaphysics -- although I'm not sure Aristotle would really want to say this -- but it is not clear that Lieb actually accepts a version of this as referring to the definiteness found in the past. Both versions would mean that everything that can happen has already happened. This could be Nietzsche's "eternal recurrence," but it would be a foolish doctrine given what we know about novelty in the evolution of life, the development of history, and the new inventions in the course of technology -- let alone new ideas in philosophy and science, although, to be sure, it sometimes seems that philosophy does not have that much to show for itself. Again, with Lieb's metaphysics, it is not clear to me where there is a provision for real novelty.

The absurdity of Plato's Theory of Forms (Εἶδει) was always the requirement that it covered all universals, natural and artificial, in concrete definiteness. Thus, Plato himself, in the Parmenides, was dismayed that the theory would require Forms for hair and dirt, which otherwise would not be consistent with the idea that the Forms represent perfection and beauty -- as long as the hair is in the shower drain rather than in the numinous glow of the shampoo commercials. And I don't doubt that many farmers and geological specialists in soils can wax eloquent about the beauty of dirt. But Plato's caution can be well taken. In our day, we would need to reflect on the necessity of Forms for televisions, dental floss, footballs, dildoes, and, really, limitless things. This begins to get silly.

So what can we do to correct Lieb's theory? The structure of possibility, necessity, natural law, and universals must reside where there is power, potential, and a sort of indefinite open-endedness. The possibility of televisions must reside in the natural laws that make its technology possible -- all the energy, materials, radiation, colors, etc. that are involved in the product and its functions. The analogies between a television camera, or any modern digital camera, and the vertebrate eye, with lens, focus, and electro-sensitive target surface, are unmistakable. We should also be conscious that camera is Latin for "room," since the photographic "camera" begins with the camera obscura, which simply projects images into a dark room, and that lens is Latin for the lentil (lentilis) bean, which was suggested by the shape of the glass created for magnification as least as early as the 13th century.

In Lieb's metaphysics, these characteristics could only reside in the future, with the reality of the future usefully restated in terms of the imperfect aspect, whose reality in the present is already and automatically included in the conception. What is required, then, is that this imperfect metaphysical foundation, which we can make the upgrade of Aristotelian matter and ὑποκείμενον, is neither entirely definite nor entirely indefinite. It simply must contain abstract structures of necessity that will determine what is possible, impossible, and necessary. There is considerable mystery involved in this, especially when we reflect that out of open possibility emerge entire structures of order, emergent order, whose novelty and unpredictability were the very things that convinced Karl Popper that the course of history, and so the course of the very development of science, was itself radically unpredictable. We start to get the feeling that sky is the limit, even as the sky itself may be without limit. The imperfect aspect cannot be properly conceived without its openness, power, and unpredictablity conceded. The opposite of this, as clearly described by Popper himself, was the rigid and deterministic process of the Hegelian Dialectic, in which the future of history, science, philosophy, religion, and, presumably, technology could all be cranked out with multiple turns of the incoherent structure of Hegelian "logic" -- a conceit inherited by Marx -- culminating in the Absolute Idea embodied in the thought and person of G.W.F. Hegel himself. All of this would have been dismissed by Kant, of course, with his own terminology as der dialektische Schein, "Dialectical Illusion."

In these terms, Lieb ends his book, actually in the "Acknowledgments," with a curious statement:

The most general idea in this essay is that what is real is an unchanging totality; there can be no additions to it, and nothing can be taken from it. This does not mean, however, that things do not change and that there are no novelties. It means that all processes and the passage of time itself take place inside the otherwise unchanging totality. [p.257]

This is an extraordinary bite of speculative metaphysics. I am not sure what there was in the previous entire book that would be the basis for it, or even what kind of datum would enable Lieb to infer anything about "an unchanging totality." Also, it is not at all obvious how "an otherwise unchanging totality" would then actually allow for either real change or novelties. This goes unexplained, and is something that wouldn't properly belong in the "Acknowledgments" anyway. Lieb does not seem sensitive to the incongruity between the terms "unchanging" and "novelties." There have been previous theories in metaphysics, as in Atomism or Empedocles, where apparent change and novelties also disappear in a reductionistic theory of "unchanging totality." But even Spinoza, whom Lieb mentions next (as I've noted above), for whom God is certainty the "totality" of reality, doesn't necessarily believe in an "unchanging" totality -- that would all depend on whether judgments about God's "perfection" allow or require novelties or not -- just the sort of muddle Kant could avoid.

Lieb's own reductionism is a metaphysics of "individuals" and "time" -- individuals who somehow become "singular," i.e. "individual," in the present, and where time somehow also produces space in the present, but not elsewhere. How individuals and time then add up to "an unchanging totality" I have not a clue. Nevertheless, however arbitrary or perplexing Lieb's ideas often seem to be, there is a fair amount here that, mutatis mutandis, we can put to use. Altering our perspective from tense to aspect is a revolution for which it is not Lieb alone who represents the ancien régime. This profoundly alters the metaphysical value that Lieb could have derived from both Plato and Aristotle, with fix-ups that I have been considering going along. After all, the idea that future time arrives inside individuals and flows out makes a lot more sense if we are talking, as Lieb is not, about an upgrade of Aristotelian matter. So we have multiple "paths not taken" with Lieb, and also a number of opaque claims and assertions, like the "unchanging totality" business itself, that need to be either motivated or rejected.

So I cannot say, and I am sorry, that Lieb has written a great book of enduring value. But it is a challenging book, although sometimes just with points of serious obscurity, and provides food for thought. Something of the sort, and a great deal more, is certainly needed for the metaphysics of time, whose real mystery continues to elude us.

Death, Light, and Black Holes

Tense and Aspect in English and Greek

The Metaphysics of Possibility

Childhood's End, the Mystery of Order

Metaphysics

Reviews

In Memoriam

Home Page

Copyright (c) 2017, 2019, 2020, 2022 Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 1

One of my last contacts with Lieb was his response to the article I had just written, "Non-Intuitive Immediate Knowledge," for the journal Ratio in December 1987. He said it was "strong," but I don't remember any other positive or critical comment. This remains my only work published in a proper philosophy journal, the last number of the original Ratio. I'm not sure I heard from Lieb again after that response, and my attention was distracted by my new teaching job, and then marriage.

Return to Text

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 2;
McTaggart's Critique of Time

While Lieb includes Whitehead (1861-1947) in his tradition of Classical philosophers, this skips over someone who continues to be noticed in the philosophy of time and about whom some comment or treatment from Lieb would have been of interest, if not expected. That was J.M.E. McTaggart (1866-1925), whose arguments against the reality of time squarely contradict Lieb's thesis and which continue to be included in discussion of the sort of "current" problems, namely about time, that Lieb urged on me.

McTaggart was one of a generation of turn-of-the-century Anglo-American Hegelians that included F.H. Bradley (1846-1924) and Josiah Royce (1855-1916) -- with the latter's name familiar to every UCLA alumnus as the eponym of the iconic Royce Hall, at the original center of the Westwood campus. Bradley's influence was something Bertrand Russell had to shake off, but it was not replaced with anything more valuable; and Russell is someone providing an excellent example of what I would called a "brilliant fool" in philosophy, whose great wit is able to conceal the vaccuous nature of his ideas.

Although McTaggart wanted his arguments to be regarded as independent of Hegelian metaphysics, we should nevertheless be put on our guard against the background and purposes of his thinking. Indeed, his famous contention that there is a "contradiction" in the analysis of time as past, present, and future should remind us that Hegelians (and Marxists) often find "contradictions" where others see merely opposition or conflict. And the very meaning of "contradiction" in Hegelian "logic" is markedly different from the way logicians ordinarily regard it, as we shall see.

McTaggart's arguments, however, do clarify some issues and do generate some meaningful problems, contributing a framework that continues to ground and provoke discussion, with the sort of so-and-so says this and so-and-so says that of current academics that I have just referenced. Most important is McTaggart's description of time as constituting or analyzable into two possible "series," the A-Series and the B-Series. His argument is that neither series justifies belief in the reality of time.

The B-Series may be the best starting point. This is time as simply a succession of states or events. Things precede and follow one another. In this view of time, it is not obvious where we would be in the present. There is nothing to distinguish one event from another as past, present, or future. This is a significant view of time because many, including Albert Einstein, believe that this is all that there is to time. If we wonder whether Einstein viewed time as just like another dimension of space, it looks like he did, and this is it. Thus, all eternity already exists, and the whole of space-time is like an unchanging crystal of reality. It is clear that this was Einstein's view because we find him comforting a berieved friend that the departed still exists as much as the living, and will always do so, fixed in eternity.

McTaggart's own critique of the B-Series is that it does not explain or accommodate change. This is true. In Einstein's eternal crystal of space-time, things have always been and will always be as they are. "Change" is something we can imagine by moving our perspective from one moment in time to another, but this is not a real physical process. Similarly, we can see here that theory allows for, or embodies, the preference in physics for the principle that time can run either way. There is no "arrow" from past to future. The equations are perfectly happy going "backwards" in time. Well, not all the equations. Physicists hit a bump when they get to entropy, but they don't have to like it; and it is not unusual for the metaphysical reflections of physicists to ignore it, as Einstein seems to have done himself.

But does Relativity treat time exactly like space? I think the answer is no. This would be the case if, as some people say, time is treated as an imaginary number, which would make it radically different from the real spatial dimensions. Stephen Hawking says that he can treat time as imaginary, but he doesn't need to; and when we look at the Separation Formula in Relativity, imaginary time is not what we see. Here time is a real number, but it is treated differently from the spatial dimensions. The sum of the spatial dimensions is subtracted from time, which means that we do get imaginary numbers for paths in space-time that exceed the velocity of light ("space-like" separation). As in engineering, an imaginary number means that something is impossible; and, indeed, Special Relativity postulates that nothing can exceed the velocity of light.

Be that as it may, Einstein could still maintain that, however different from space, time is nevertheless no more than McTaggart's B-Series, with the implication of eternity and bi-directionality preserved. Not only does this eliminate real change, as McTaggart says, but it leaves us with no clue where we are in that eternity. Every point in time is ontologically identical to every other; and if we were asked what point represents the present time, there is no internal evidence of such a distinction.

Nevertheless, there is a feature of the B-Series that is essential to the concept of change. We only get from one moment to the next in terms of the Laws of Nature. One event cannot be followed by just anything, although we can imagine (with Hume) such a nightmare world, or even portray it in film. But what events can follow other events is instead strictly controlled. If I drop the ball (standing on the earth, with space under it, and without the ball being attached above, etc.) it will fall. Thus, wherever the present moment may be, getting from one moment to the next is not an arbitrary succession. It is lawful succession, as Einstein would have heartily agreed (believing that quantum mechanics violated this principle).

The identity of the present comes in the A-Series described by McTaggart. This series is simply distinguished by the relation of past, present, and future events. And this gets us to the heart of McTaggart's argument against the reality of time, since he says that the existence of the same event in past, present, and future is a contradiction, discrediting the very idea of time. Thus, the argument is presented as a reductio ad absurdum, which proves the falsehood of its thesis. However, we must not forget that McTaggart is a Hegelian. There are really no reductiones ad absurda in Hegelian "logic." Each contradiction generates a "synthesis," which is not a falsehood at all, but simply the next step in the Hegelian Dialectic.

If, like most logicians, we regard this business as itself absurd, what if we take McTaggart's argument, as most do, as a genuine attempt at a reductio ad absurdum? Well, one of my logic professors, Irving Copi, once said that, faced with an apparent contradiction, one can see about resolving it by making a distinction. With past, present, and future, the distinction is evident on the face of it. Making the Aristotelian distinction between essence and accident, we would want to say that what are essentially the same events are nevertheless different by the accident of being in past, present, or future. They are not different at the same time, which is what is essential for a contradiction.

Now, McTaggart evidently wanted to argue that somehow this approach is circular, that we are defining what time is by using time. However, if we have already tried to define time by using the B-Series, where the differences between past, present, and future are unidentifiable, then obviously we have already demonstrated that time can be defined without past, present, or future. So there is nothing circular about introducing them in the A-Series.

Also, it is a question of method. Is McTaggart using a deductive, axiomatic method for his study, or is he approaching time in a descriptive and phenomenological way? It cannot be deductive and axiomatic if we arrive at a conception of time as the B-Series, with which Albert Einstein was quite content, which would mean that the concepts of past, present, and future do not logically follow from the bare concept of time itself, which is presumably the axiom of our system. That would be a very Hegelian procedure. Hegel believed that even the axioms of geometry were analytic, as with Leibniz, which means that substantive truths follow from the bare meaning of a concept. Furthermore, if the concepts of past, present, and future do not follow from the concept of time behind the B-Series, we also have the point of McTaggart impeaching the B-Series as not accommodating change. This implies that change is an essential part of the concept of time, to the point of discrediting derived ideas that are insufficient. But we must then ask where McTaggart would have gotten that concept.

Indeed, the general understanding of McTaggart's system seems to be that it is phenomenological, which does have a nice Hegelian ring to it. Nevertheless, as we have seen, it cannot be that Hegelian, since the Dialectic doesn't really allow a reductio ad absurdum argument. On the other hand, if we help McTaggart out by saying that this is a phenomenological study in the Husserlian sense, then it will not allow a reductio ad absurdum either. That is because Husserl's Phenomenology was to simply look at the phenomena and discern (however that works) the essential features. Looking at time, one indeed tends to discern a difference between past, present, and future (also, see the following discussion in the main text about the difference between tense and aspect) and change. There is no room there for circularity. It gives us the intuitive conception of time that all the theories try and unpack.

McTaggart also seems to have argued that past, present, and future contradict each other because they exist equally and so (somehow) simultaneously. The contradiction here would be in the premise, where "simultaneous" is already excluded by the postulation of past, present, and future. Simultaneous things are at the same time, which means that such a time be entirely in the past, in the present, or in the future. But McTaggart's idea that past, present, and future events exist equally is contadicted by the (phenomenological) observation that things exist in the present but no longer in the past, and not yet in the future. McTaggart has a problem admitting some kind of reality to the past and future without that reality being the same as the existence of the present. Indeed, this is a good metaphysical question, but it is probably not one to be resolved by a merely phenomenological approach. This is where McTaggart would need to put his metaphysical cards on the table, and this is what he (or his supporters) do not want to do if the arguments about time are going to be independent of Hegelian, or any, metaphysics.

While Kant could happily leave a theory of possibility in the shadows of things in themselves, Hegel did not have that luxury. But is not clear in Hegel's metaphysics what accounts for possibility. The Dialectic generates history as well as concepts, but there actually is nothing like Aristotelian matter to provide the potential for anything of the sort. This will also be a problem for Irwin Lieb, who evidences some frustration and impatience at being entangled with "possibilities." But no robust or complete metaphysical system can gloss over a theory of potential or possibility -- unless one, of course, sticks to Einstein's B-Series, where future possibility is identical to actuality in eternity.

After reviewing McTaggart's arguments, Lieb may not have lost that much by overlooking them. He already faces the metaphysical problem of past, present, and future; and McTaggart really isn't very helpful with that. But it would have nice to have at least seen what Lieb thought of McTaggart's arguments.

Return to Text

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 3

Immortal physicist Richard Feynman went through a period in his life when he tried to keep up with all the physics literature being published, and so with "current" problems and discussion. After a while, he realized that he wasn't getting anything done by way of his own work. Thus, other people's ideas and problems were not really helping him get any new ideas. So Feynman decided to forget about keeping up with the literature and just pursue his own Muse. I don't know if this meant that he stopped going to physics conferences, if he ever had, but that diversion probably would have been just as distracting.

To write his book on time, Irwin Lieb seems to have been taking Feynman's advice, probably without realizing it. But where Feynman came up with original ideas in quantum electrodynamics and earned a Nobel Prize, I'm not sure that Lieb comes anywhere near the equivalent originality, even if there were a Nobel Prize in philosophy. Lieb is owed an "A" for effort and he does have some original perspectives, but the danger of Feynman's strategy is that one thereby joins the company of every nut and crackpot who has ever written up their own private madness. I may enjoy books claiming that the Emperors of Japan are the successors of the rulers of the Lost Continent of Mu, but this sort of thing will not make any permanent contributions to human knowledge and understanding.

My own experience is that most new literature in philosophy is pretty worthless. But there are exceptions. It is just hard to identify what may prove valuable. I try to attend the Rutgers Epistemology Conference just to see what people are talking about; and, of course, in Jerrold Katz I found a recent academic philosopher with significantly new and important ideas. Since Katz has been ignored by subsequent academic philosophy, I am not therefore persuaded that, in general, it has much of value to contribute. In turn, when I find a philosopher writing about moral dilemmas without any original ideas, and without reference to treatments that I have had posted on line for twenty years, and which I know at least some people have read, I am persuaded both of my own originality and of the unimaginative conventionality of "current" discussions. An example of the mixed value of recent work may be found with the dilemma of The Miners that came up at the 2019 the Rutgers Conference.

Two episodes stand out in my memory of my class with Irwin Lieb. One was when Lieb arranged a visit by the physicist E.C. George Sudarshan (b.1931), the originator of the idea of "tachyons," hypothetical particles that travel faster than the velocity of light. Although no such particles have been observed, they are now a standard part of science fiction. It sounded like Sudarshan was a personal friend of Lieb's. His most striking comment to the class was that the equations of Relativity look like those of fluid mechanics. So space-time was something that flowed, like water. In his theory, Lieb seems to think of time like that.

The other episode was simply a story that Lieb told. During a visit on a nuclear submarine -- I don't remember that Lieb clarified what he was doing there (he had been in the Navy during WWII, although as an aviator) -- the ship was diving. The hatch above the conning tower evidently had not closed properly, and water began to rain down on the bridge crew. The point of Lieb's story was about command. The dive was being conducted by the Officer of the Watch, or of the "Deck," the OOD (which may be rendered "Office of the Day" when the ship is in port). The Captain of the ship waited a long moment for the OOD to give the commands to reverse the dive and surface the ship. But the OOD had frozen, as can happen. Giving the officer his chance, the Captain then took charge and, well, saved the ship. Watch officers are usually, in effect, in training. There is even an officer-in-training under the Officer of the Watch, the JOOD or "Junior Officer of the Deck." I've forgotten the context of the story, but the picture of the scene and the issue made a strong impression. Years later I saw a documentary about a nuclear submarine. The order "submerge the ship" was given by the Captain, and then -- something never shown in movies -- the order passed down the chain of command, and the acknowledgments came back up, more like the scene of shooting the noon sun in a Patrick O'Brian novel.

Return to Text

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 4
Future Contingency

In Chapter IX of On Interpretation, Aristotle discusses whether propositions are necessarily true in relation to time. He begins:

In regard to things present or past, propositions, whether positive or negative are true of necessity [ἀνάγκη] or false. [18a, Aristotle, The Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, translated by Harold P. Cook, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard University Press, 1938, 1962, p.131]

The future, by contrast, is different:

When, however, we come to propositions whose subjects are singular terms, while their predicates refer to the future and not to the present or past, then we find that the case is quite changed. [p.133]

After some discussion, Aristotle concludes, "We are driven, therefore, to concluding that all affirmations and denials must either be true or be false" [ibid.] -- this is the principle of the Excluded Middle. From this he concludes, however, that even propositions about the future must also be by necessity, so that:

Now, if all this is so, there is nothing that happens by chance [ἀπὸ τύχης] or fortuitously [ὁπότερ᾽ ἔτυχεν]; nothing will ever so happen. But [ἀλλ᾽] all events [ἅπαντα] come about of necessity [ἐξ ἀνάγκης], and of contingency there is none [καὶ οὐχ ὁπότερ᾽ ἔτυχεν]. [pp.132-133; translation and word order altered]

Aristotle reaffirms this saying, "And in consequence future events, as we said, come about of necessity" [p.135]. Note that "chance" here is τύχη, Tyche, or Fortuna in Latin, meaning "luck, good fortune, favor of the gods," etc. Contingency is otherwise expressed with the verb τυγχάνω, "to hit, to hit upon, meet with, to happen, befall," etc., which we see here in the second aorist ἔτυχον. What goes with this is ὁπότερος, "which of two." So ὁπότερ᾽ ἔτυχεν might literally be "whatever happened."

However, he soon says something different:

All this is, however, impossible. We know from our personal experience that future events may depend on the counsels and actions of men, and that, speaking more broadly, those things that are not uninterruptedly actual exhibit a potentiality [τὸ δυνατόν], that is, a 'may or may not be" [καὶ τὸ εἶναι καὶ τὸ μὴ εἶναι]. [pp.137-139]

So it is necessary that propositions about the future be true or false, but which it is to be is not a matter of necessity:

φανερὸν ἄρα ὅτι οὐχ ἅπαντα ἐξ ἀνάγκης οὔτ᾽ ἔστιν οὔτε γίνεται, ἀλλὰ τὰ μὲν ὁπότερ᾽ ἔτυχε.

Thus it is clear that not everything is or takes place of necessity; but cases there are of contingency. [pp.138-139, translation altered]

Aristotle's famous example is whether a sea-battle, ναυμαχία, will take place tomorrow. Of the propositions that it will or it won't, one will be true; but they will not be true by necessity until the battle has or has not happened.

Aristotle's analysis captures features of the modality of time. Once something has happened, it cannot unhappen; and since it cannot then be otherwise, it is a matter of necessity. However, when it is a mere possibility, it can be otherwise, and so truths about it, which are not necessary for some other reason, will be contingent. This business caught the attention of Mediaeval philosophers, like al-Fârâbî, and seems to call for little improvement today, however little attention is devoted to its implications. We might expect an examination from Lieb, but we actually don't get one.

However, we might wonder why there is an asymmetry in the metaphysical structure. Why are propositions about past and present necessary, but only those about the future contingent? We might realize that there is a contingent feature of the present also. The window may be open, but I can close it. There is no necessity to its being open, in the sense that it cannot be otherwise. It can be otherwise. So how can we account for this? That's easy, really. The necessity is in the perfect aspect, while the contingency is in the imperfect. Since both perfect and imperfect can be in the present tense, we see aspects of both necessity and contingency in the present. If something has happened, it is too late to stop it; but it may well not be too late to change it. On the other hand, the perfect as a past tense has necessity but not possibility, while the imperfect as a future sense has possibility and contingency but no necessity. Neither Aristotle nor Lieb are aware of the aspect system, and neither takes advantage of its features.

Return to Text

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 5

It perhaps should be noted that Hebrew and Arabic inflect for gender in both the second and the third person, unlike Indo-European languages such as English, Greek, or Latin. Thus, the forms cited above are masculine, while in Hebrew we also find , qâṭlâh, "she has killed, killed," and , tiqṭōl, "she is killing, will kill." In Arabic we get the feminine forms , faʿalat, "she has done, did," and , tafʿalu, "she is doing, will do."
HebrewArabic
Perfect

qâṭal

qâṭlâh

faʿala

faʿalat
Imperfect

yiqṭōl

tiqṭōl

yafʿalu

tafʿalu
In both Hebrew and Arabic we see the use of the feminine "t" that is also the suffix in feminine nouns. As in nouns, the "t" can become an "h" at the end of independent words -- although we see this here in Hebrew but not in Arabic. These features were already active in Ancient Egyptian, as is the interesting device of suffixes for the perfect and prefixes for the imperfect.

As far as I've noticed, neither Hebrew nor Arabic (nor Egyptian) are attacked as embodying "sexist language" because of these gender inflections. Indeed, accusing the Arabic language, the sacred language of the eternal Qu'rân, of some sort of feminist political crime ("sexism") probably would strike most Muslims as offensive -- not to mention if there were any attempt to alter the form of the language, the way in politically correct circles "Latino" and "Latina" are now replaced by the non-Spanish and unpronounceable "Latinx" (they seem to be saying "Latin X"). This is not popular.

Reticence about treading on that ground may be consistent with the silence of prominent feminists about the status of women in Islam. They often have embraced the idea that "Islamophobia" means any criticism of Islam or identification of the problem of Islamic Terrorism. Of course, criticism of the status of women in Islam goes way beyond any issues involved in Terrorism. The more disturbing reflection is that these attitudes signify the regard by the Left for both Islam and Terrorism as allies against America, capitalism, Western Civilization, white people, Christianity, Zionism, and, often enough, Jews -- this despite widespread attitudes and practices in Islam that are deeply inconsistent with "progressive" Leftist positions on women, homosexuality, slavery, etc. After all, the enemy of my enemy is my friend; and to the Left, as well as to the Ayatollahs, America is the greatest Enemy that has ever existed.

Return to Text

Past, Present, and Future, by Irwin C. Lieb; Note 6
Individual and Singular

The distinction between a universal and a singular is introduced by Aristotle in Chapter VII of On Interpretation:

Of things there are some universal [τὰ μὲν καθόλου] and some individual or singular [τὰ δὲ καθ᾽ ἕκαστον], according, I mean, as their nature is such that they can or they cannot be predicates of numerous subjects, as 'man' [ἄνθρωπος], for example, and 'Callias' [Καλλίας]. [17a-b, Aristotle, The Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, translated by Harold P. Cook, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard University Press, 1938, 1962, pp.124-125, boldface and color added]

A striking thing here is that the translator has given us a choice of "individual" or "singular," as though they are synonymous, when translating a single expression in Greek, καθ᾽ ἕκαστον, which parses as κατά, "according to," ἕκαστος, "every, every one, each, each one." So, at the origin of logic with Aristotle, there is no distinction between "individual" and "singular," which themselves clearly come from Latin terms meaning "not to be divided" (individualis) and "single" (singularis). The burden of proof is on Lieb to motivate his separation of the meanings, which he does not do, except to assume what is to be proven, i.e. that they are different, and can be assigned to all times and to the present alone, respectively.

The expression for "universal" is of interest. This originates in the same kind of construction as that for "individual":  κατά, "according to," ὅλος, the "whole." Putting the case to agree with the preposition gets us κατὰ ὅλον, "according to the whole." Then we get the final vowel of the preposition elided, which looks like this καθ᾽ ὅλον, with the final tau of κατὰ aspirated; but then the whole phrase contracts into one word, *καθόλος, "on the whole, in general," which according to Liddell and Scott is only used in the genitive, καθόλου, as in our example. This ends up being much more familiar with a derived adjective, καθολικός, "general, universal," or in Latin catholicus, i.e. "catholic." The Roman Church is "universal" -- Una Sancta Catholica et Apostolica Ecclesia.

Popes and Patriarchs

Return to Text